4.0 Chalmers' own demolition job on materialism rests on a
number of explicit arguments and tacit presuppositions.
It relies on a distinction between low- and high- level
facts; on a distinctive notion of reductive explanation;
on a tricky and protean philosopher's term of art,
"supervenience"; and on an implicit (and ultimately folk-derived?) theory of perception of a macroscopic world. There are advantages, but also potential problems, with all four of these
concepts. I'm going to argue that most errors in the
philosophy of mind and consciousness - and the reasons
for the intractability of the mind/matter relation,
derive from a misconceived notion of perceptual
experience.
4.1 First, however, it will be as well to accept such a
multi-tiered framework of explanation on its own terms.
Does it disqualify, not just materialism (yes!), but any
form of monism (no, IMO), from prospectively exhausting
the furniture of the world?
4.2 Crucial to Chalmers' argument against the possibility of
a reductive explanation of our minds is the claim that
conscious experience does not logically supervene on the
physical. Were mind logically to supervene on low-level
facts, or were the notion of "high-" and "low-" level
facts untenable, or were our notions of supervenience
itself subtly incoherent or misleading, then the argument
would fail. And if the equations of physics don't rule
out stuff with - or consisting in - intrinsic subjective
properties, then Chalmers' project of showing the
failure of logical supervenience will depend on there
still being an "independent logical space" (p35)
for human minds to vary independently of these
microphysical facts. Granted both the equations of
physics and the intrinsic properties of the stuff
they describe, I'm going to argue contra Chalmers that
there is no way experiential manifolds can fail to
"supervene". Experiential manifolds [a.k.a. minds,
a.k.a. multitudes of DNA-driven egocentric virtual worlds
churned out in genetic host-vehicles by evolution]
support a distinctive mode of experience, nominally
insentient matter. This typically gets contrasted with
another mode of experience, which is merely a restricted
extra-somato-sensory type of consciousness. An
explanatory gap opens up when we try to explain one by
reducing it to the other. Posed like this, the problem
can't be solved. One could no more ontologically
reduce a symphony to a landscape.
4.3 If it can't be ruled out except by fiat that complex
minds do supervene on "low-level" facts - though
they most certainly don't supervene on materialist
factoids - then there is a more radically conservative
and ontologically parsimonious option than property
dualism, epiphenomenalism, pan-informationalism, or any
jury-rigged system of further options. The ontology of
monistic panpsychism in effect denies any "explanatory
gap" between "high-" and "low-" level
facts - if such an idiom is to be retained. To be a
feasible proposal, the low-level facts will of course
need to be essentially different in character from the
tenets of classically-inspired materialist orthodoxy. The
difference is in their intrinsic nature: the relational
properties of micro-qualia will be captured by a type-identical formalism. This is because the inherently
phenomenal micro-stuff must still accommodate all the
prodigious experimental, explanatory and technological
successes of contemporary physical science. More positively, they
are far better capable of redeeming the prodigious
failures of science; which tend to be far less-touted,
particularly by the drug-naïve.
4.4 The existence of a ubiquitous and minimal what-it's-likeness as intrinsic to the stuff of the world, or better, as
the stuff of the world itself, is an option which
Chalmers does seriously and sympathetically
consider. Yet he ultimately rejects it. I want to
understand, as best I can, his reasons for doing so; not
least because - unsettlingly - Chalmers (see below)
gives the best exposition I've come across of the family of
positions one of which I'm advocating. For it is quite consistent to
agree with the materialist that QM is mathematically
(Gödelian complications aside!) complete and yet to argue that
what presently pass for physical concepts "can be
given topic-neutral analyses that might pick out
underlying phenomenal properties" (p135; Chalmers is
here expounding the quasi-Russellian position of the late
Grover Maxwell).
4.5 This approach, Chalmers acutely notes, delivers a form of
idealistic monism which is radically unlike Berkeley's.
For on this view, "the world is not supervenient on
the mind of an observer, but rather consists in a vast
causal network of phenomenal properties underlying the
physical laws that science postulates" (p155).
Chalmers notes that "Physical laws can be interpreted
as laws that connect intrinsic properties (or properties
constructed out of these) to their relational profiles
(or to complex relational structures). We are led first
to the relational structure of the causal network, and
only slowly to the underlying intrinsic properties."
4.6 Indeed, "No set of facts about physical structure and
dynamics can add up to a fact about phenomenology"
(p118). Yet any conclusive inference to the failure of
logical supervenience, were it to succeed, would depend
on physics additionally granting us an understanding of
the noumenal essence of the stuff whose behaviour its
equations exhaustively describe. And this is what physics
just doesn't do.
4.7 So why does Chalmers reject such an account which he expounds
so incisively? He acknowledges that "Physics tells us
nothing about what mass is, or what charge
is; it simply tells us the range of different
values that these features can take on, and tells us their
effects on other features"(302). He grants that
"Physical theory only characterises its basic entities
relationally, in terms of their causal and other
relations to other entities" (p153). He's prepared to
canvass an interpretation that avoids both
epiphenomenalism and Cartesian dualism. He's willing to speculate that phenomenal
properties "implement" the dispositions that physical
theory deals in. Yet he still doesn't buy monistic idealism.
If our ignorance qua physicists of what "breathes
fire into the equations" really is unqualified, however, then
recourse to, at the very least, a topic-neutral construal of the QM
formalism would seem inescapable. The equations, as before,
exhaustively describe the behaviour of the pro tem
topic-neutrally construed stuff of the world. Our
enforced agnosticism about the stuff's intrinsic nature
means one might just as well allege that
insentience as much as sentience fails logically
to supervene on its properties. We simply don't know
whether it does or doesn't; the panpsychist is betting,
he fancies with inside information, that it does.
4.8 I'd guess Chalmers would argue that even if it naturally
supervenes, it doesn't logically supervene.
Unfortunately, any serious discussion of the issues here
would demand at least a treatise on modality and
doubtless a better cocktail of nutritional supplements. In this
piece, I shall just for once have to dogmatise.
4.9 The notion of non-epistemic possibility, or any
substantive distinction between x and (redundantly IMO)
necessarily x, is empirically ungrounded and
philosophically ill-motivated. In practice of course it is indispensable. I'm just not convinced it can do all the philosophical work Chalmers wants it to do. For unfortunately contingency is a deeply
mysterious and ill-defined notion. Any bid to show that
anything could really be different from how it
is founders in assuming what it seeks to prove.
There are no real grounds for believing that what exists could
naturally or logically be otherwise. If sometimes we
don't understand why something couldn't be
otherwise relative to certain background conditions, then
no deep ontological consequences flow from our epistemic
frailties. Logical possibility is often taken to be
possibility in the broadest sense ["It is useful to
think of a logically possible world as a world that it
would have been in God's power (hypothetically!) to
create, had he so chosen." (p35)] Yet the fact that
we find the need to resort to such conceits is revealing.
It shows the problems our intuitive conceptions bring
when made to bear independent ontological weight.
4.10 Surely, the counter-argument might run, it needn't
logically be the case that everything is the way
it is? Well, it depends on your conception of logic and
your choice of primitives, axioms and operators. With the
right primitives and operators, perhaps everything
else logically supervenes, albeit non-provably. Intuitively,
one is liable to find the notion of anything
existing logically absurd. The empirical evidence
suggests one is massively in error. So one's concepts are
wrong. Wholly at sea, one can't simply junk one's entire
categorical raft altogether [Neurath]. So one
tries to rework parts of it while guessing it is all rotten. Any
sort of existence strikes me as daft; but I've had to
learn to live with it. So assuming that something somehow
analogous to 0 ought to obtain as the default
condition, I look rigorously to define
what precisely would have had to obtain for 0 to be the
case as decency suggests it should. If it does seems
nonsensical and absurd that anything exists - though
something-or-other manifestly does - then one seeks to
explicate one's intuitive concept of 'nothingness' or
complete absence of properties so it becomes formally
equivalent to zero. On this analysis, our pretheoretic idea of "no properties at all existing" as commonly understood is muddled. But something analogous to this notion i.e. zero net properties - is not merely intelligible, but true; and what we call the world is the expression, mathematically describable by physics, of this timeless logical principle. Zero is a surprisingly rich concept
of astonishing fertility in maths, however queasy one may
feel about using anything which smacks of reifying
"Nothing". Given the properties of this ill-understood
primitive, however, then an attempt can be made to
extract everything - logically, physically,
phenomenologically, and mathematically - from its unique
status.
4.11 No, as it happens, I wasn't on acid at the time I was
delivered of this little epiphany; just feeling
intellectually desperate. For at times even much of
physics can seem remarkably akin to stamp-collecting.
More to our purposes here, however, Chalmers still has
work to do to show that our minds fail logically to
supervene on the micro-facts.
4.12 Substantive possibility aside, even epistemic possibility
is more problematic than one would wish. Again relative
to certain background conditions, one can apparently
conceive of all sorts of things as being otherwise than
how they are. This is a far from straightforward idea. Inevitably, simply to get off the ground, such a notion already presupposes that one's mental episodes
can possess - as distinct from simulate - an otherwise
ineffable feature of the Multiverse known in the trade as "broad" content. This is the marvellous sort of relational content that
"ain't in the head". All rational debate must assume something like it, even if no one quite knows what 'it' is. Calling it 'naturalistic' demystifies without illuminating its nature. In the case of
contingent propositions, the problem is far worse. For one can't even invoke
causal co-variation (etc) to legitimate their force. Yet
unless realism about subjunctive conditionals
can be reconciled with scientific naturalism, then one
hasn't even really conceived of the purported
referents of one's thought-episodes as being different
from how they are. Scientifically legitimating
indicatives is hard enough; subjunctives pose
difficulties which are orders of magnitude worse.
4.13 Ascribing to some of one's real, spatio-temporally located
thought-episodes the capacity to access real contingency is a practical necessity. Yet once again it's worryingly like a (sometimes) heuristically useful
fiction - and just the sort of snow-job at which natural
selection, played out over the aeons, excels. Even
Everett's Multiverse, a false friend to the possible
world enthusiast, simply is a superposition, not a
set of alternate, absolutely non-interfering realties. [Actually, our
little multiverse is arguably only one vacuum fluctuation among
many, just "one of those things that happen from time
to time". If so, then cornucopian googolplexes of
multi-verses may proliferate all over the place.
Scary] Yet in no case does this entail that there is
unactualised potentiality (or whatever) for anything
being otherwise than it actually is. The notion of real
contingency in any form is adaptive. In default of any substantive grounds for swallowing it, this is grounds for harbour ing greater suspicion of its credentials, not less.
4.14 If contingency isn't taken to rest on some psychologistic
criterion of actual conceivability, but instead on a
notion(!) of possible worlds, then it might(!) seem to enjoy
greater objective warrant. Yet the very concept of a
possible world again presupposes the existence of the
contingency which it purports to explain. [In all
honesty, these one-liners should be flagged to warn the
unwary that there is rather more to be said]. And granting
God any say in the matter, even as a philosophical
facon de parler, opens up a different can of worms
altogether.
4.15 How does this review's scepticism about the force of (obscurely) literal contingency tie
in with the alleged failure of logical supervenience of
the conscious mind on low-level micro-facts? Well, in
reality, Chalmers, like most of us, inevitably
does entertain intuitions in a general sort of way
about what the basic stuff of the world broadly can and
can't be. These intuitions sit uncomfortably with any
professed ignorance of noumenal essences. "Physics
tells us nothing about what those [intrinsic] properties
might be. We have some vague intuitions about these
properties based on our experience of their macroscopic
analogs - intuitions about the "massiveness of mass, for
example -..."
4.16 Insofar as these "macroscopic analogues" really
are inherently similar - and not just functional
counterparts - then perhaps our intuitions could be
justified; and the failure of supervenience vindicated.
Yet the concept of a macroscopic analogue needs exploring
carefully. It rests, in practice, on the notion that we
are presented with, or granted direct epistemic access to, or
apprehend transparently [or whatever], a
mind-independent macroscopic world. The virtual realist favours myriad data-driven simulations of local real-world
macro-patterns which our individual minds are running.
A folk-sanctioned everyday macroworlds, on the other hand, is supposed to be
an extra-mental reality on the other side of one's skull
(and not simply on the other side of a causally co-varying
skull-surrogate of a somato-sensory homunculus) which
perception mysteriously allows us communally to access. By
contrast again, inferential realism, although committed
to a vast mind-independent Multiverse as the best
explanation of our autobiographical virtual worlds, is
not committed to the existence of a distinctively
macroscopic stratum of reality whose properties
supervene on layers "beneath" it. 'Virtual'
strata, yes, real strata, no. Instead, macroscopic
neo-cortically-generated material objects, located in the
coherently awake mind, are our reified counterparts of
recurrent patterns in fields of what-it's-likeness in the
inferred Multiverse beyond. Perhaps!
4.17 Moreover, even if we did have such innocent access to
Reality, in just what respects are "macro-" properties
analogues of the intrinsic properties of their
"underlying" micro-constituents? If tepid grey porridge is
supposedly the extrinsic analogue of intrinsic
phenomenological mind [ pah!], then what faith can we
have that our alleged "extrinsic" and relational handle
on the properties of particles/fields/superstrings(!)
captures their intrinsic nature any more faithfully?
4.18 For reasons to be elaborated, if panpsychism is to seem
remotely viable and a Chalmers-inspired dualism averted,
two controversial conditions must be fulfilled. The first
is a concession of the feasibility - if not
inescapability, given our present ignorance - of a topic-neutral reconstrual of the formalism of physics. The
second is the falsity of orthodox perceptual direct
realism.
4.19 I'd argue that Chalmers is pushed into a semi-sanitised and
non-interactionist dualism rather than the panpsychist
monism to which he might otherwise lean mainly because he
implicitly relies on an untenable background theory of
perception. It's this theory, I think, which leads to his 'inside'/'outside' dichotomy and his proposed ontology of ubiquitous information states linking 'internal' micro-phenomenology and 'external' physics. The Conscious Mind doesn't offer a
full-blooded account of its author's philosophy of (what
passes as) sensory experience and its relationship to the
rest of the world. Yet the assumptions of an implicit
theory creep into his story in a number of places. In a
crucial passage, Chalmers alleges that the panpsychist
position entails a "dualism of 'accessible' and
'hidden' physical properties" (p136). The intrinsic properties
of the world-stuff posited by the panpsychist aren't the
"properties physics deals with directly"(153).
4.20 Yet what are the properties physics (physicists?) deal
with directly? In what sense are they
"revealed"(p136)? Is this an allusion to [our
notional] shared access to a supposedly token-identical
[and not merely type-similar] macroscopic world? This
presumably self-subsistent macroworld would be where
public experiments are performed. Some of its
notional high-level properties would serve as analogues to
microphysical primitives. Or, on the other hand, is the
revelatory metaphor an allusion to explicitly represented
properties of basic microphysical entities whose
mathematical description the theorists play around with? If the
latter, then the argument is undercut by the need for
topic-neutralism given our present absolute ignorance of
"what breathes fire into the equations and makes there
a world for us to describe." [Or do we know something
Hawking doesn't? Maybe. But not this...].
4.21 If the 'directness' and 'accessibility' of physical properties is indeed an allusion to a notional shared macro-world, then
the position slides into a descendant of folk-style
perceptual direct realism. And as the phenomena of e.g.
phantom limbs, near-death experiences, Penfield's
electrode studies, ketamine-induced out-of-the-body
episodes etc corroborate, one doesn't even have direct
access to the body of one's extra-psycho-cerebral host
organism external to the mind's somato-sensory-homunculus, let
alone exotic pastures further afield. As Kant once quipped, it's
a small world. More anecdotally, let's suppose that, for
instance, one is gazing down at the visual body-image one
normally intimately consorts with ['my' body(-image)] when not
out of one's head on the dissociative anaesthetic
ketamine. In this condition, then the prospect of
abandoning science for the intellectual equivalent of tea-leaf reading seems more tempting than it probably does
right now. For the perceptual realist, undergoing
a ketamine-induced OBE must seem like a clear refutation of
scientific materialism; though I'd argue that it's materialism and
perception that ought to be retired, not quantum
mechanics. For what it's worth, I find "in-the-body"
experiences are intellectually at least as odd as "out of
it" modes of existence. This is because organic mind
seems too warm to allow coherent, multi-modally-bound
states; and coherent states would seem to offer the best
hope for superposing (pre-fronto-cortical-] self-concepts
and the different [visual, kinaesthetic etc] modes of
body-image.
4.22 Chalmers own commitment to the IMO fatally misleading
presuppositions of perceptual direct realism is revealed
in such phrases as "How could [consciousness] possibly
arise from lumpy gray matter?"(p3) "Whoever would
have thought that this hunk of gray matter would be the
sort of thing that could produce vivid subjective
experiences? And yet it does." (p251). Yet does
it?
4.23 When one is dreaming, for instance, and one inspects the
properties of a brain, then that lump of porridge which
one's body-image manipulates isn't generating the
sentience of another mind. It is simply a fleeting
coalition of psychons of one's own mind-dust as described by the
canonical equations. When one is in that peculiar state of
consciousness self-flatteringly known as being "awake", then a
more-or-less type-identical brainy experience would be
activated only under the tightest selection by peripheral
psychoneural impulses. These are distally caused via the activation of surface transducers in the host vehicle by
patterns in the external world. Possibly, in that external world, an
experimentalist or neurosurgeon is working with electrode
probes in a laboratory or operating theatre. In this
setting, the brain which the neurosurgeon's etc own
visual-cum-somato-sensory body-image is manipulating in
his experiential manifold will be serving as the causally
co-varying analogue of distinctive macro-patterns of
sentience in his [alert, locally anaesthetised] patient's mind/virtual world.
Unreassuringly, the reality must be vastly more
complicated than the prose used to express it.
Yet what sounds natural on the ear would only be a telling advantage if our
concepts were the gift of God; and even then, absentee
landlords are not to be trusted.
4.24 By way of illustration again, it is easy to slip into
thinking of consciousness as being by its nature ethereal
and nebulous. Chalmers remarks on how it is
"diaphanous" and "intangible"(p3). Yet
tangibility and opaque solidity are highly distinctive
properties of certain modes of consciousness. In one's
dreams, for instance [invoking dreams is convenient when
one wishes temporarily to avoid using question-begging
accounts of perception], one is not simply conscious
of a rock, a sunset, a table, or a brain. These
rocks, sunsets, tables and brains are fleetingly-bound
experiential manifolds of sentience themselves. [I think
this self-referential thought qua a fleetingly
bound experiential manifold of sentience myself].
Rocks, even dream-rocks, are thoroughly opaque and
tangible. One can ham it up playing Dr Johnson all one
wants. One can even feel the pain. One just won't enjoy
any greater degree of success at refuting idealism, whether Berkeleian or naturalistic, than the
robust-minded Doctor. Real philosophy is hard work.
4.25 Now when one "wakes up", the
weighted connections which mediate such dream-phenomena will,
just as yesterday, be activated in the normal way
only by peripheral, environmentally-triggered
stimulation. [In dreamless sleep there's no experiential
manifold; just an incoherent quasi-punctate psychic
sludge]. These weighted psychochemical patterns of one's
waking hours don't inexplicably cease to manifest the
same type of solid, abrasive etc modes of consciousness which
dream-rocks and tables do at night. [One's life may regain a
certain narrative drive; but that's another story.] Nor
do these patterns of excitation take on instead the role of mere
resonant vehicles [or whatever] for putative real world
access. If one doubts their daytime status, then allowing
electrode-stimulation of one's awake mind/brain is a
splendid way of getting disabused. Another is to dim the
selecting peripheral inputs, drop a lot of acid, and
grant one's virtual worlds a greater measure of daytime
independence than they usually get the freedom to express. My advice would be: don't do it; not yet at any rate.
4.26 To recap. If there were any such spectacle as single,
mind-independent macroscopic world - rather than
selfish DNA-driven egocentric travesties of salient
fitness-relevant macro-patterns in the superposition of
a unitary Multiverse - then the conceptual division of
reality into ontological levels could do real
explanatory work.
In fact, folk-inspired theories of
perception are multiply misleading in other respects
too.
4.27 First, perceptual realism (as distinct from inferential
realism or some sort of VR-inspired data-driven
simulationism) commits us to the existence of a non-branching, quantum-theoretically anomalous macroscopic
world. This invites physically ill-grounded talk of
dynamically collapsing wavefunctions.
4.28 Second, perceptual realism invites a division of the
world into a hierarchy of levels on which the whole
notion of reductive explanation and its inferred panoply
of sub- and super- venience relations depends. For
analytic philosophy's spatial metaphors of "high-"
and "low-" level facts, and the vexed notion of
supervenience with which they are so often associated,
are an artefact. They turn on our tendency to divide
reality into one tangible and manifest macroscopic world,
and an invisible microphysical counterpart which underlies
it. Invoking supervenience (once pithily dubbed
"epiphenomenalism without causation") is
admittedly preferable to a tendency to make "low-level" events literally cause "high-level"
events (cf. Searle) with which they are supposedly
identical. For brain states can't cause the very same
mental states with which they are alleged to be one and
the same. They can cause subsequent states, which
confusingly may then be known under a mental as well as
physical description. Unfortunately the usual
philosophical vocabulary serves as a perennial temptation
to extract ontological rabbits from an epistemological
hat.
4.29 In either case, it's worth recalling that if QM is
complete then the Multiverse exists as a single awesomely
big superposition. For sure, given the evolution of a hot,
simple and symmetric universe via spontaneous symmetry-breaking phase transitions into the complex universe of
this particular era, the world from our perspective
simulates in varying degrees the evolution of
different levels. Non-equilibrium thermodynamics throws
up an increasing number of [what may be more-or-less systematically
interpreted as] virtual layers. It is sometimes very
useful to treat these persisting or recurrent patterns as
though they were ontologically autonomous echelons of
reality with their own laws - just as one might divide
up the different "virtual" machines running on a
computer. Yet the world itself doesn't literally
instantiate, as distinct from progressively
simulate, different layers. The fundamental
fields/strings/n-branes/psychons or whatever just wiggle
energetically in different ways taking on different
values. They contrive, I think, to bewitch some of their
throwaway quick-and-dirty patterns into taking an extended family of
stratigraphical metaphors more literally than it
deserves.